Thursday, October 16, 2008

Philosophical Persistence (Bear With Me On This!)

My relationship to philosophy is cordial. I understand that for others, philosophy is simply insufferable, with all its complexities and quagmires. I acknowledge this everyday with my wife. Yet, I love philosophy and am not put off by people's perceptions of it. I will endure every form of ridicule for its sake.

The reason, I think, for my affinity to philosophy is its magnetism in terms of how it survives. That is, how it can persist despite its obsession with formulating questions and not (direct) answers. This is the part of philosophy that I find personally more attractive than theology. Theological thought attempts to answer philosophical questions (for better and for worse), whereas philosophy is content to live with the irreconcilable questions of human existence.

Undoubtedly, I find, as a theologian, the idea of existing without any belief in God to be full of many existential difficulties. But this does not keep me from admiring those who live their lives morally without any notion of God. There is ethical valence here. Acting morally without the need for God seems to be a stronger notion of morality than what Christians typically offer. This is why Kierkegaard, as a Christian, was an absolute genius with his "teleological suspension of the ethical" In short, this means that there comes a point where people of faith must be willing to risk everything, including moral imperatives, for a relationship with God . (His famous example is Abraham who went against Semitic law all for the purpose of serving God). Like I said, I recognize the potency of living morally without the need for God. This does not mean, however, that I am ready to assume it.

All this to say that I have found yet another philosophical gem that has drawn my serious attention, even to the point of distracting me from my classwork (How terrible!). What I found was Hans-George Gadamer's Truth and Method, a book about how to interpret human experience. Specifically, the part I am reading now has to do with aesthetics. I am sure many of you are wondering why I find this important enough to write about it in my blog (and why I am unnecessarily boring you with my findings). But I think his thought bears repeating here because his philosophy is vital for understanding how art affects us.

That being said, I will try to keep it short, and if you are still with me until the end, I will be very grateful, because I think what he has to say on art affects us in more ways than we think. It might even help us to rethink how we approach things. Here it goes....

Fundamentally, Gadamer wants to get rid of the notion that our experience of art is something that is cultivated (through culture) and brought to a situation. Instead, what he wants to do is bring our attention to the "temporality of art," that is, he wants to resist the idea that art can be timeless as well as the notion that people interpret art subjectively. That may seem strange, but what Gadamer attempts to do is get rid of the notion that we come to art with experiences, cultivated by our society and our past experiences, in order to appreciate art. He calls this way of approaching art as "aesthetic consciousness." Yes, that may sound confusing, but you really do not have to fully understand what that means in order to understand what he is trying to say about art.

Gadamer believes that art can be better understood as "play". What he means by play is that when a person is playing a game they are not playing in order to achieve an end necessarily, but rather because they are drawn into play and they become a participant in play's constant repetition (it is an endless means). In this way, the subject of play is not the player herself, but "play". If the person was the subject then this would be opting for the above belief that a person brings with themselves an experience in which to draw from. Gadamer finds this insufficient because it denies the immediacy of the event itself. Playing also entails something that responds to our activity. (Imagine a kitten playing with a ball of wool, they play with the ball of wool because it responds to its action. In that way, it is inviting.)

This response though is risky for the person because all play presents itself with serious possibilities or undetermined outcomes. (For instance, we watch football games because they present undetermined outcomes. This is what absorbs us as we watch 4th quarter drives. We do not know the outcome. As such, we are absorbed into the game. We may not be personally playing the game, but this does not mean that we are not participating in it.) This is essentially what Gadamer wants to get at in our experience of art and beauty. The piece of art becomes "immediate" to us and we participate in art because art is something that invites us into itself. I know speaking of art as having its own being is confusing, but think of it this way: when we listen to music we are ushered into its world. By doing this, we participate in the music. We are not playing the music personally, but it is drawing us into itself. In this way, Gadamer counters the notion that experience of art is something that we bring to the situation. The belief that "beauty is in the eye of the beholder" is an example of this wrongful subjectivism in art.

The reason why approaching art with subjectivism is inadequate is that it ignores how art presents itself to us. It invites us into itself. This is why we experience such a high when we listen to music, or see a beautiful sunset; we are actually drawn into the art. This is why he speaks of art as play, because play entails participation.

Play also entails transformation. That is, when we play, we are transformed into a different person. In that sense, art is powerful for us because it convokes a change in who we are.

The problem with "aesthetic consciousness" is that when it seeks to find what is truly beautiful it attempts to differentiate between our cultivated notions of the beautiful and the work of art itself. It compares these two and comes up with an analysis of whether or not the artwork is beautiful. This is problematic, and it affects us more than we know.

For example, when we are judging a performance of a play by Shakespeare, say Romeo and Juliet, based upon our previous experience of reading the play we are using "aesthetic consciousness". We are separating the original written work from the performance that we just experienced. By differentiating these two, we deny the temporality of art, its immediacy. Another example would be judging a particular musician's new recording by previous recordings. This is once again separating the work from its mediation.

Gadamer wants to say instead that you cannot separate a work from its mediation (or, a written play from its performance). Doing so would put a method on art that is not fit for art. Like, for instance, using scientific methods to determine how beautiful something is. That is impossible! THIS IS WHY HE WANTS TO AVOID THE CRITICAL NATURE OF AESTHETIC CONSCIOUSNESS. When we seek to determine whether something is aesthetically pleasing, in other words, we are basically assuming that one can correctly interpret a work of art. Of course, no one would say that there is something seemingly beautiful in a certain piece of music that does not exist in another piece of music. So why would we attempt to criticize something based on our preconceived notions of what is beautiful? This approach either assumes that "art is timeless" or that all "art is subjective." Both assumptions are, without a doubt, untenable and useless.

In this way, Gadamer is a genius. He wants to interpret art not from the perspective that one can come to a correct interpretation of art (like the subjectivists assume, in that they either judge art from their own experience or their own culture) and the perspective that art is timelessly beautiful but he wants to focus instead on how art affects us. In this way, our experience of art is different than that which assumes that we can come to a work of art with experiences. This latter notion of "experience" is possessive, in that we have something. (For example, think of this experience in the sense that "McCain has more military experience than Obama") The former is an experience in which something outside of us draws us into itself. (Think of this sense of experience as, "Van Gogh's artwork sets off so many emotions in me.")

Indeed, this analysis of art means that true experience of art comes from the object itself (in other words, this object becomes the subject) not us.

I find this extremely stimulating and helpful. I have always noticed how hypocritical some people are of movies and music, to the point that our notion of the aesthetic becomes a game of criticism. Art is art, let it affect you. Do not try to base it on how you think beauty should be presented, but rather allow the art itself to present itself to you.

Once again, I thank you for following me throughout this post. If I have confused you, do not think you are dumb. I may need to clarify some things. So, please, by all means....comment away!

8 comments:

  1. Caleb you have too much time on your hands. Haha I have been accused of the same.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Do you think it would be accurate to say that instead of us possessing art, we should let the art possess us in that moment?

    Now, what about taking this one step further. Do you think that this applies to literature? Specifically, religious literature, such as the scriptures?

    I can see it to a certain extent in reading fiction. It's captivating and you can lose yourself in some books. (which also makes me wonder if this means we should criticize how we define whatis good and bad writing as well.)

    ReplyDelete
  3. Gwahir,

    Yes, I think to a certain extent Gadamer would apply this to literature. He does after all apply it to written plays.

    Gadamer is concerned with truth, and how we come to that truth.
    Because of this, he rejects any methodology. Truth, for him, cannot simply be captured by any method.

    So, with that said, i think it does apply to religious literature since it is replete with religious symbols.

    About bad and good writing, Gadamer says that if we let the idea of "cultivation"--that is, of creating parameters of what is aesthetically pleasing and what is not--we "make it easy to write a good poem, but hard to be a good poet." In other words, by getting rid of what we consider to be "alien and crude" we make it impossible for the freedom of art to take place.

    That is certainly true, because if you look at our greatest poets, most of them created the genre or brought it into popularity. Our problem is that we have taken these forms of art and made them the standard of all art.

    ReplyDelete
  4. I'm not all that enamored with Gadamer, but I'm too tired to explain it fully. I just don't think he's all that original. I agree with him in some places, others I don't.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Well, this book was written in the 60's. I think for then it was original. Maybe not so much his critique of aesthetics but more so his rule for hermeneutics.

    ReplyDelete
  6. I like the analogy of art (and theology) as a play. I have long viewed theology as a beautiful play. Theology is truly an art. However, I have not extended this thought to the realm of art in general.

    I have a couple of clarifying questions:

    1.) If we are to let the art present itself to us, then am I correct in thinking that the interpretation of the art will constantly change as time goes on and as new people see the work of art?
    2.) Would I be correct in thinking that I could come away from the work of art when I was 19 and have a different interpretation (because of my newfound life experiences) of the art than I did when I was 12?

    P.S.
    Take a breath dude!

    ReplyDelete
  7. Coppess,

    To answer your two questions.

    1. Interpretation of art never arrives at a correct interpretation. Therefore, people will have different interpretations of art.

    Something to take into account for interpretation, Gadamer states, is the fact that our past does have an affect on our present interpretation.

    By this Gadamer does not mean to say that we posses these experiences and can make them build on one another. Rather he says that these past events widen our horizon.

    For Gadamer, it is events that are the subjects, not people. If it was people it would be subjectivism. He wants to avoid this. Subjectivism in this respect would deny the "object" or "event" validity, making them inconsequential.

    So, the answer is both yes and no. Yes, because we never arrive at the truth of a thing. No, because the subject is the event not the person, and if the event is speaking then it will conjure up only certain responses.

    I know that is confusing, but Gadamer wants to balance both perspectives.

    2. Yes, you would be correct. Gadamer talks about past experiences as important for present interpretation. Though, as I said before, he wants to avoid the idea that we posses these experiences. Rather he wants them to be a part of an integrative process where our horizons are widened by each experience. This makes it difficult to state the Truth of something definitively. But he does not want to use any method, including our experiences, to come to some notion of Truth. This does not mean he believes truth to be relative, but rather that our grasp of truth is rather fallible and relative to our experiences.

    ReplyDelete
  8. BTW, Josh, if you want a great example of Theology as a grand Drama, you should look into Hans Urs von Balthasar who came up with Theo-Drama. Very interesting stuff. He makes all of theology a drama of God's relationship with humanity

    ReplyDelete